17
Of
Cruelty and Clemency,
and Whether It Is Better to Be Loved or Feared
Proceeding
to the other qualities before named, I say that every prince must desire
to be considered merciful and not cruel. He must, however, take care not
to misuse this mercifulness. Cesare Borgia was considered cruel, but his
cruelty had brought order to the Romagna, united it, and reduced it to
peace and fealty. If this is considered well, it will be seen that he was
really much more merciful than the Florentine people, who, to avoid the
name of cruelty, allowed Pistoia to be destroyed. A prince, therefore,
must not mind incurring the charge of cruelty for the purpose of keeping
his subjects united and faithful; for, with a very few examples, he will
be more merciful than those who, from excess of tenderness, allow
disorders to arise, from whence spring bloodshed and rapine; for these as
a rule injure the whole community, while the executions carried out by the
prince injure only individuals. And of all princes, it is impossible for a
new prince to escape the reputation of cruelty, new states being always
full of dangers. Wherefore Virgil through the mouth of Dido says:
Res
dura, et regni novitas me talia cogunt Moliri,
et late fines custode tueri.
Nevertheless,
he must be cautious in believing and acting and must not be afraid of his
own shadow, and must proceed in a temperate manner with prudence and
humanity, so that too much confidence does not render him incautious, and
too much diffidence does not render him intolerant.
From
this arises the question whether it is better to be loved more than
feared, or feared more than loved. The reply is, that one ought to be both
feared and loved, but as it is difficult for the two to go together, it is
much safer to be feared than loved, if one of the two has to be wanting.
For it may be said of men in general that they are ungrateful, voluble,
dissemblers, anxious to avoid danger, and covetous of gain; as long as you
benefit them, they are entirely yours; they offer you their blood, their
goods, their life, and their children, as I have before said, when the
necessity is remote; but when it approaches, they revolt. And the prince
who has relied solely on their words, without making other preparations,
is ruined; for the friendship which is gained by purchase and not through
grandeur and nobility of spirit is bought but not secured, and at a pinch
is not to be expended in your service. And men have less scruple in
offending one who makes himself loved than one who makes himself feared;
for love is held by a chain of obligation which, men being selfish, is
broken whenever it serves their purpose; but fear is maintained by a dread
of punishment which never fails.
Still,
a prince should make himself feared in such a way that if he does not gain
love, he at any rate avoids hatred; for fear and the absence of hatred may
well go together, and will be always attained by one who abstains from
interfering with the property of his citizens and subjects or with their
women. And when he is obliged to take the life of any one, let him do so
when there is a proper justification and manifest reason for it; but above
all he must abstain from taking the property of others, for men forget
more easily the death of their father than the loss of their patrimony.
Then
also pretexts for seizing property are never wanting, and one who
begins to live by rapine will always find some reason for taking the goods
of others, whereas causes for taking life are rarer and more fleeting.
But
when the prince is with his army and has a large number of soldiers under
his control, then it is extremely necessary that he should not mind being
thought cruel; for without this reputation he could not keep an army
united or disposed to any duty. Among the noteworthy actions of Hannibal
is numbered this, that although he had an enormous army, composed of men
of all nations and fighting in foreign countries, there never arose any
dissension either among them or against the prince, either in good fortune
or in bad. This could not be due to anything but his inhuman cruelty,
which together with his infinite other virtues, made him always venerated
and terrible in the sight of his soldiers, and without it his other
virtues would not have sufficed to produce that effect. Thoughtless
writers admire on the one hand his actions, and on the other blame the
principal cause of them.
And
that it is true that his other virtues would not have sufficed may be seen
from the case of Scipio (famous not only in regard to his own times, but
all times of which memory remains), whose armies rebelled against him in
Spain, which arose from nothing but his excessive kindness, which allowed
more license to the soldiers than was consonant with military discipline.
He was reproached with this in the senate by Fabius Maximus, who called
him a corrupter of the Roman militia. Locri having been destroyed by one
of Scipio’s officers was not revenged by him, nor was the insolence of
that officer punished, simply by reason of his easy nature; so much so,
that some one wishing to excuse him in the senate, said that there were
many men who knew rather how not to err, than how to correct the errors of
others. This disposition would in time have tarnished the fame and glory
of Scipio had he persevered in it under the empire, but living under the
rule of the senate this harmful quality was not only concealed but became
a glory to him.
I
conclude, therefore, with regard to being feared and loved, that men love
at their own free will, but fear at the will of the prince, and that a
wise prince must rely on what is in his power and not on what is in the
power of others, and he must only contrive to avoid incurring hatred, as
has been explained.
|