Greek Philosophy
Socrates & Plato
1
Philosophic
Directions
Refinement
and Conversion
1 Philosophy
is the love of
wisdom. To love wisdom is to pursue wisdom, and the two approaches to
wisdom are notable.
If you are on the right road, your approach depends on continuing in an
effective way. But if you are not on the right road, or if you mistake
your road for the right road, then you need to change directions. Much
useful philosophy results from refining assumptions, from modifying views.
But Socrates and Plato focused intently on conversions, beginning with
destabilizing tradition, convention and common sense. WHAT we see depends
on HOW we see. Socrates and Plato focus energies on changing HOW we see.
2
Socrates
Ethical
Appeals
Aristotle
divides persuasive appeals into three categories ethical, rational and
emotional. Ethical appeals, according to Aristotle, are not the mere
attention to good and bad attitudes and actions. Judging ethical appeals
depends on the perceived character of the speaker. Pre-eminent among
philosophers as a credible speaker is Socrates. Socrates invites
reconsideration and conversion. Like Aeschylus’ practice of recognition,
Socrates questioning initially leads to disorientation, a motion away from
appearances, sensations, conventions, to an indeterminate openness to
discovery. Socrates’ character and reputation draws attention to this
interest and focus, sometimes positively, sometimes critically.
What
makes Socrates an engaging voice? A combination of irony and conviction.
Socratic irony plays variations on the weak foundations underlying
conspicuous authority. The Delphic Oracle identified Socrates as the
wisest of mortals. Puzzled, since he was painfully aware of his ignorance,
because his mind gravitated to questions, not to answers, because his
years of questioning and his innumerable discussions with a range of
Athenian and foreign participants had raised more questions, Socrates
eventually concluded that his
distinction was to be aware of his ignorance. Without doubt, the discovery
of a fresh approach necessary to approach true knowledge would be
impossible.
Socrates’
character and personality generated controversy. Eventually an Athenian
jury would sentence him to exile or to death, and an Athenian to the last,
he drank the hemlock which ended his mortal life. Charges against him
included disrespect for religion, an inappropriate reliance on natural
science, and a disrespect for tradition. Moreover, his appeal to young
Athenians in formative periods of life, threatened Athenian tradition and
traditional Athenians. He took Athens as the rare city which allowed such
critical activities, choosing death as a loyal Athenian to life elsewhere.
:He could not and would not stop questioning, stop his quest. His interest
in questioning all belief (as an approach to discovering beauty and truth)
appeared as an attack on prominent Athenians and as an attack on Athens.
Socrates’
influence depended as much on his character as on his philosophical
approaches. His disinterest in material possessions and in status combined
with his attention to the mind and spirit. Among his most memorable
activities was an event during the retreat from Persian forces after heavy
casualties at Potidaea. A leader in organizing dispirited soldiers for
retreat, Socrates, before joining the retreat, paused, lost in thought,
his attention elsewhere. Plato’s Appolodorus recalls this memorable scene when
guests assembled at a symposium learn that the absent Socrates appeared
once more lost in thought as one of the guests passed him on the way to
the party.
3
Pericles
Rational Appeals
Pericles
considered Athens as a distinctive city, a city in which characters and
activities like those of Socrates drives Athenians to defend their way of
life at all costs. Athenians, leading the defense of Greece when Persians
invaded (in 490bc and in 480bc) could not imagine living under
restrictions of traditional cities (including Sparta), where acting in
accordance with how people previously acted, living with institutions like
previous institutions, took precedence over the discovery of new character
and new institutions, as well as a new sense of history inviting
adaptations to changing circumstances. Pericles’ invitation to love
Athens, rather than idolize the bravery of the greatest of soldiers,
parallels Socrates love not just of philosophical beauty and truth, but
more of the practices necessary to discovery, the character necessary for
conversion. Pericles’ funeral oration invites audiences not merely to
support democracy, but more to practice philosophical approaches to
history.
If
mourners at a funeral, threatened with invasion, death and slavery, are to
survive, they must appreciate the way of life defended by deceased
soldiers. They must think, as well as act, as Athenians.
View
events historically. How do funeral practices arise? How do traditions
relate to circumstances? In new circumstances, how may new traditions
arise? If plague threatens Athenians, how does it arise? What courses does
it follow? What peculiarities are discernable worth the consideration of
others, present or future? Pericles argues that Athenians, falling in love
with Athens will distinguish themselves from traditional citizens
including Spartens: they love not just their city, but the character and
practices that make Athens a new world
4
Plato’s
Cave
Emotional
Appeals
Plato’s
Parable of the Cave still offers participants a surprising experience.
Imagine yourself in the most compelling of times, places, company and
activities Plato suggests. Your circumstances, person, and company appear
real in large part through sense perceptions. But consider an alternative.
Observe another person, chained in immobility, looking at the polished
walls of a cave. Images move, grow, diminish, approach and depart. In this
projection, not unlike a movie screen, mere projections attract
involvement, arouse passions. What appears most engaging and convincing to
us may be no more than superficial appearances. Plato’s projection lamp
is a flickering fire behind his audience. His images are objects on a
ledge. As the fire flickers and the objects arrange and rearrange, their
projections on the cave walls in front of us are the only images we have
ever reacted to. We are immobile, but our immobility never appears to us,
since flickering images provide action. We are immobile, so we never have
an alternative perspective to reveal the originating activities which
create our sensational world.
Were
we to turn back, however, the projection lamp, too bright for our
unaccustomed eyes, would blind us, would painfully burn our eyes. Leaving
the cave, of course, we would not see and appreciate a world far more real
than that projected world we had taken as our only experienced world. We
would be even more disabled. Only with time might we accustom our senses
to new inputs, might we “see” not merely new objects, but the way in
which sunlight makes possible not only the appearance of objects, but also
the ways in which they move, grow, relate, diminish.
Outside
the cave, of course, engaged in real sunlight, with illuminated objects,
with an awareness not just of things, but also of relationships, of
originating principles, we note with pity the inhuman restrictions
limiting, chaining, enslaving the residents of the cave. But those within
the cave, knowing nothing else, have no such thoughts and feelings. Their
world, the only world they experience, appears neither more nor less real
than our own. But we, Plato suggests, are not observers of cave-dweller,
ourselves perfectly situated in our won real world. Our world itself is
the cave. And we, like the cave-dwellers we have imagined, will find
discovering our superficialities a painful experience.
5
Plato’s
Line
Rational
Appeals
To
leave our cave we must discover a new world. How are we to do so? By
distinguishing between belief and knowledge, by moving from the sensible
to the intelligible. Could we once have the experience of true
relationship Plato believes, we would be unlikely to find satisfaction in
the objects, company, activities and assumptions we previously
experienced, assumed, used and valued. How are we to experience such a key
to conversion? For Plato mathematics offers just such a conversion.
Through a geometrical demonstration, we may discover the light bulb turns
on.
Among
the most distinctive of all Athenian activities is the systematic
discovery of geometry. Egyptians, among others, had extensive knowledge of
shapes, knowledge sufficient to engineer architecture as memorable as any
ever produced. Knowledge sufficient to justify boundaries yearly erased by
the flooding Nile, returning chartered land to productive use. But
consider the pentangle associated with Pythagorean communities. Take a
pentagon. Inscribe a five-pointed star. Note the inscribed pentagon. Now
inscribe once more the star. Take the original pentagon. Extend the sides,
noting your circumscribed star. Joining the points, form the circumscribed
pentagon. Your figure has no outermost or innermost limit. The shape grows
and diminishes according to a generating principle. Christian Platonists
will later explore Pythagorus’ active emblem through Solomon’s knot, a
reincarnation of the Pythagorean pentangle which appears, for example, on
Gawain’s shield in medieval romance.
Plato’s
Meno offers a preliminary approach to his divided line. Return for the
moment to the Nile valley. You have a square plot of land. You wish to
sell a square of your plot half the size of your total square. Of course
you can approximate such a plot. Divide the square into quarters. One
quarter isn’t enough. Divide each quarter into quarters. 9/16ths is too
much. Divide each sixteenth into quarters. 1/4, 5/8, 7/16, 31/64 . . .
Every step approaches closer to the desired plot. But every step
alternatively will be just too small, or just too big. (You probably
“know” that the square root of 2 is irrational, that it can never be
measured in perfect fractions of 2. But Greek geometers “see” such
limitation through demonstration, and what they see they know as an
experience, not merely as an alleged “fact”). Now mark the midpoints
of each side of our original square. Joint these points to form an
inscribed square. See how each quarter-square encloses two equal triangles
(fold square to see how each triangle covers the other). Your inscribed
square encloses four equal squares, leaving four additional equal squares
to form the circumscribed square. We can see our inner square as exactly
half the area of our original square. Unlike the square which “looks”
close to half the original square, a sensible half-square, this square is
we “see” as half the original square is an intelligible square.
Plato’s
divided line invites us to a more surprising experience: the discovery of
a division which has most unlikely generative properties, properties
including those which unravel Solomon’s knot. Take a line and divide it
unequally. Assume the longer side to be to the left of the division, and
consider this segment to represent the sensible experience. Assume the
shorter side to be to the right of the division, and consider this segment
to represent intelligible experience. Now divide the longer segment
unequally, such that the lengths of the two segments are proportional to
the lengths of the original line segments. How are we to make such
divisions?
Form
a pentagon and then extend sides to form the circumscribed star. Each arm
of our star, together with a side of our pentagon forms a divided line.
Now consider the remaining arm of our star. It forms a segment of the line
also containing our original two segments. We could explore a procedure to
produce these segments clearly with an intelligible procedure, but such
would require following Euclid at some length. For the moment assume the
ratio of segments to be (the square root of 5 + 1)/2. You can take a
square; divide in half horizontally; form the diagonal of the upper
square; rotate the diagonal to form a vertical line. Now the lower half
segment of the original square plus the rotated segment forms the longer
unit and the bottom of the original square forms the shorter segment of
our divided line. But “seeing” such relationships will take energy and
time.
Perhaps,
like our half-square procedure, we can approximate such a division.
Consider the numbers generated by adding successive numbers such that each
addition sums the two previous numbers: 1, 1, 2, 3, 5, 8, 13, 21, 35, 56 .
. . Some two millennia after Pythagoras Fibonacci initiated consideration
of peculiar features of this sequence, features which include convergence
on Plato’s divided line, as well as modeling of stock fluctuations under
particular conditions.
Why
does Plato remind all who seek his guidance to study mathematics? First,
because mathematics is intelligible: it discovers not facts, but the
principles through which significant facts manifest themselves.
Mathematics is systematic, is structural, is intelligible. Next, because
astonishing regularities far from expected
may reveal generating principles for appearances. Consider the
infinite sequence of integers. In 1742 Goldbach conjectured that every
even number greater than 4 is the sum of two primes. Every number can be
generated from the multiplication of two primes (with the addition of 1
for odd numbers). To date no proof for this conjecture has appeared, but
no exceptions have been found. Reconsider such numbers as generated by
prime numbers (numbers not divisible by other numbers. Generating small
numbers from primes may not appeal ( since many primes appear among small
integers), but as integers grow larger, primes grow increasingly scarce.
For large numbers, a relatively tiny number of primes will suffice to
create all such numbers.
Geometry,
like geography, seeks to make the earth intelligible. Geography maps the
world, and maps require principles. Geometry enables participants
to make intelligible (as well as practical) their world. As head of the
great library of Alexandria. Eratosthenes noted, filed and considered the
widest range of views available in his time. Hearing that
a well existed in Cyrene (modern Aswan) where light reached the
bottom on one day of the year (the longest day, the summer solstice),
Eratosthenes made intelligible the size of the earth. In Cyrene the sun
was directly overhead (we might consider the overhead sun to indicate that
Cyrene lies on the earth’s equator, but Eratosthenes lacked both globe
abd encylopoedia). On the longest day, Eratosthenes placed a stick in the
ground pointing directly upward. When the shadow cast by the stick was
shortest (indicating the sun was highest), he marked the length of shadow.
The angle at the top of his triangle was about 7 degrees. He understood
that the circumference of the earth was about fifty times the3 distance
between Alexandria and Cyrene. Allowing for
uncertainty as to the precise length of the stadia he used as a
unit in his recorded distance, his intelligible circle was remarkably
close to 25,000 miles. Galileo will later “see” the circumference of
the moon, and the distance of the moon from the earth.
6
Philosophical
Skepticism
Plato and Gorgias
Plato’s
intellectual competitors (notably Gorgias) were sophists who shared with
him the skeptical character which precedes fresh discovery, without which
conversion could not arise. Sophists believed that man is the measure of
all things. Man is the measure not because man is omniscient, certainly
not due to omnipotence. In the absence of perfect inspiration human truths
will be partial, will be relative. Open debate, in the mind, in the market
place, in the courts, will not reveal truth. But debate can shape more
productive attitudes and actions than rigid tradition or unreflective
common sense. Choices among beliefs may be decided not by habit, and not
by objectivity, but rather by consideration of plausible consequences of
competing approaches. Aware of fools and knaves, the former imagining they
alone possessed true knowledge, the later manipulating subjects with the
pretence of certainty, Gorgias sought to educate his followers in fruitful
rhetoric, a skill crucial to political as well as personal advancement.
Plato
shared with Gorgias a distaste for tradition, convention or common sense
as sufficient evidence of truth, but believed true directions towards
wisdom were intelligible, however demanding travel would be. Plato further
believed that the consequences of taking rhetoric as the guide for
actualizing desires, personal and social and political, would be
disastrous.
Philosophy
for Plato is the pursuit of Wisdom. Serious practitioners of philosophy
develop powers of skepticism to limit the appeal of tradition, of
convention, of common sense. But serious philosophers also must keep in
mind credible experiences where the approach to objective truth, where the
experience of attending true beauty, not mere theorizing, are actual,
personal experiences. Plato shares with Gorgias a sceptical a scepticism
towards traditional understandings of truth. But he invites followers to
experience through geometric demonstrations experiences which reinforce
approaches to systematic truth.
Leaving Plato's Cave: The Divided Line
We
will join Socrates at Plato’s Symposium to share in the pleasures
of instruction and the instruction of pleasures.
Plato’s
Art of Love: The
Symposium
|